Philosophy of
Science: Operationalism
Professor
Jeffery Kasser produced a series of 36 lectures through The Great Courses entitled Philosophy
of Science.
These
are my notes, commentary, and synopsis from Kasser’s lectures. The author of this blog highly recommends
this course as a high quality lecture on the philosophy of science.
One may
purchase the entire course here.
Operationalism was part of a spectacular attempt, followed
by failure, of logical positivism (or logical empiricism). To understand operationalism, we must first
discuss the effect of Einstein on the thinking about science at that time.
The principle of relativity
pre-dated Einstein. If two people are
floating in empty space, they are moving with respect to one another without
regard to any other objects – any other objects are not needed to define their
motion with respect to each other. A
similar principle applies when one is on a ship at sea on smooth waters within
a room inside the ship with no windows.
Objects move within that room as if they were in a room on land. If I were running away from a guy named Jim
at 10 miles per hour, and Jim threw a baseball past me at 30 miles per hour, then
relative to me, the ball would be moving 20 miles per hour. This idea worked out fine for all known
objects at the time except for one: light.
No matter how fast an object moved, light always appeared to move away
from that same object at the same speed in all directions. The core problem for science at that time was
the relativity of all other objects, and the non-relativity of the speed of
light.
Einstein proposed a radical
solution to this problem. He did not
ignore the results; he accepted the measurements. He instructed his peers that they needed to
reevaluate core assumptions about space and time. The mistake was to assume that we had clear
ideas about time and length. Einstein’s
solution accepted the data by allowing time and length to expand and
contract. Our mistaken assumptions could
be fixed if we focused upon the experience and measurements of the
investigation. This idea of focus upon
the measurements and the data had a profound influence upon the scientists of
that time.
P. W. Bridgman attempted a
solution to this problem in light of Einstein’s proposals. His solution is called Operationalism. Operationalism insists that one’s concepts
and ideas should never supersede looking directly at nature – looking directly
at the measurements and the experiences of the scientific investigation. We must always ensure that something in
nature – something in the experience of the investigation – clearly corresponds
to our concepts.
Operationalism defines scientific concepts in
terms of operations we must perform to measure or observe things corresponding
to the concept. Length, for example, is not
a property inherent in an object, as one may suppose; but a series of operations
or procedures one uses with a device such as a meter stick. For operationalism, this is all length is –
similarly for any other property. One
must also ponder that this also means that all different procedures from
measuring the same property are, strictly speaking, different operations; using
a meter stick versus using radar are two different definitions of length. Bridgman proposed that some phenomena are
directly observable and need no operational procedure.
Operationalism has some problems
which seem to defy solution. How does
one specify that during the performance of an operational procedure one does
not have any additional factors affecting the measurement? For example, how does one design an operation
that eliminates forces of magnetism and radiation pressure for the measurement
of an object’s weight upon a balance scale?
There is a strange and open question as to how one can claim that a
mercury thermometer and an alcohol thermometer measure the same characteristic
of temperature when the operational procedures are not the same. Another example Kasser points out is the measurement
of temperature on the Sun. We have no
measurement device to perform this operation (we are told). Thus, what we call temperature on the surface
of the sun is not an operational definition, but assumes temperature as a
concept apart from a measurement device, which is against the point of
operationalism.
Brief Commentary
It seems that we cannot get away
from abstract concepts. Many in science
claim that it is strictly empirical and focused upon observation and data. However, even a basic, observable idea such
as length is an abstract concept. One
must use abstract reasoning to understand that length measurements of a radar
and length measurements of a meter stick have in common the exact same concept
of ‘length.’
The old Problem of Universals in
philosophy has been around for thousands of years, and nobody can get around
it, as far as we can tell. For example,
nobody can point in space to a physical object corresponding to the idea of ‘the
square root of two.’ One must use
non-physical abstract reasoning to understand the square root of two. And, nobody can provide empirical evidence of
the existence of the square root of two.
However, only a strange person would deny the reality of the square root
of two. The same problem seems to apply
to science: all its units are abstract ideas.
Empirical claims do not rely strictly on observation. Science cannot ignore these metaphysical
problems.
No comments:
Post a Comment